Forma de citar este artículo en APA:

López-Astorga, M. (2022). Intersection of sets and inter-understanding between portuguese and spanish. Perseitas, 10, 431-448. DOI: https://doi.org/10.21501/23461780. 3950

INTERSECTION OF SETS AND INTER-UNDERSTANDING BETWEEN PORTUGUESE AND SPANISH

Intersección de conjuntos e intercomprensión entre portugués y español

Artículo de investigación científica y tecnológica

DOI: https://doi.org/10.21501/23461780.3950

Recibido: mayo 3 de 2021. Aceptado: julio 7 de 2022. Publicado: 8 de julio de 2022

Miguel López-Astorga

Abstract

This paper describes a study about inter-understanding between Portuguese and Spanish. Based on Peano’s work, the study resorts to the logical relation of intersection between sets and applies it to words in Portuguese and Spanish meaning the same. The material is the abstract of a psychology paper. Each of the words in that text, which is written in Portuguese, is compared to its corresponding Spanish word by means of the relation of intersection. This is made by considering the letters in the words to be elements in sets. The results show the potential that this methodology can have to provide percentages of inter-understanding between the two languages (and between any pair of languages).

Keywords

Inter-understanding; Peano; Portuguese; Relation of intersection; Romance languages; Spanish.

Resumen

Este artículo describe un estudio acerca de la intercomprensión entre el portugués y el español. Basándose en el trabajo de Peano en 1904, el estudio recurre a la relación lógica de intersección entre conjuntos y lo aplica a palabras en portugués y en español con el mismo significado. El material de análisis es el resumen de un artículo de psicología. Cada una de las palabras en ese texto, que está escrito en portugués, se compara con su palabra correspondiente en español por medio de la relación de intersección. Esto se hace considerando que las letras en las palabras son elementos en conjuntos. Los resultados muestran el potencial que esta metodología puede tener para establecer porcentajes de intercomprensión entre los dos idiomas (y entre cualquier par de idiomas).

Palabras clave

Español; Intercomprensión; Lenguas románicas; Peano; Portugués; Relación de intersección.

Introduction

At present, there are many works about linguistic inter-understanding (e.g., Bertelli, 2016; Chávez Solís & Erazo Muñoz, 2014; Decandio & Dolz, 2015). As it is well known, that concept refers to the understanding of a language by a person that does not speak it. However, that very person’s mother tongue is, to an extent, akin to that language.

On the other hand, there are also several studies on the similarities and differences between Portuguese and Spanish (e.g., Almeida Filho, 1995; Aparecida Duarte, 2005; Ceolin; 2003; Vázquez Diéguez, 2011). This issue is important; the proximity between these two languages has caused a great interest in the field of inter-understanding. In fact, the relations between Portuguese and Spanish are subject matters in many works about inter-understanding among romance languages (e.g., Bonvino et al., 2015).

The present paper tries to move forward in these directions. Nevertheless, it describes a study resorting to a methodology based on formal logic. When Peano (1903) proposed latino sine flexione, he carried out an analysis of the levels of similarity of several languages. Those languages were English, French, German, Spanish, Italian, Russian, Greek, and Sanskrit. A very relevant point is that his methodology was developed from the logical relation of intersection of sets (Peano, 1904). That was made in the study presented below. Nonetheless, the relation of intersection was used in this new study just to determine levels of similarity between Portuguese and Spanish. That allowed providing predictions about percentages of potential inter-understanding among these two languages.

There are already works indicating possible predictions regarding inter-understanding between Portuguese and Spanish (e.g., López-Astorga, 2017). Those works have a strength: they are derived from a contemporary cognitive theory with a strong empirical support. That theory is the one of mental models (e.g., Byrne & Johnson-Laird, 2020; Khemlani et al., 2018; López-Astorga & Torres-Bravo, 2020). However, the purpose of the research reported here was different. Those works often refer to situations in which inter-understanding can be easy, as well as circumstances in which inter-understanding can be hard. But the study below, rather than describing cases in which inter-understanding can happen or not, tried to offer an approximate minimal percentage of understanding in a particular activity: when a person that speaks only one of the two languages mentioned reads a text written in the other language. To work in this way, a paragraph, which is the abstract of a scientific paper written in Portuguese (Gouveia et al., 2002) was addressed.

Thus, the structure of the present paper is as follows. First, it comments on Peano’s idea and explains how that idea was applied in the study. Second, it presents the results obtained. Finally, those results, the limitations of the study, and possible lines for further research are analyzed.

The relation of intersection between sets

The relation of intersection is known in logic. The symbol ‘’ expresses it. This relation refers to the common elements among sets. For instance, let A and B be two sets.

A = {a, b, c, d}

B = {c, d, e, f}

The elements of A are a, b, c, and d. On the other hand, the elements of B are c, d, e, and f. Therefore, the intersection of A and B consists of the elements c and d. This is because c and d are the elements that A and B share. This can be expressed in this manner:

A B = {c, d}

Following Peano (1904), this operation can be made with words. That allows identifying the letters that those words have in common. Words (1) and (2), which also appear in Table 2, can be taken as an illustrative example.

(1) Raciocínio

(2) Razonamiento

These two words have the same meaning. Both of them mean ‘reasoning’. However, (1) is a Portuguese word and (2) is a Spanish word. The idea is to deem both (1) and (2) as sets whose elements are their letters. Thereby, (1) can be considered to be set C, and (2) can be considered to be set D.

C = {r, a, c, i, o, c, i, n, i, o}

D = {r, a, z, o, n, a, m, i, e, n, t, o}

The relation of intersection between C and D is obvious.

C D = {r, a, o, n, i, o}

The study described below adopted a conventional thesis: if the intersection of the letters of two words with the same meaning in different languages is equal to or greater than 2/3 of the letters of each word, any speaker of only one of those languages can understand both words. This is what (3) points out.

(3) If P Q ≥ 2/3 of P and ≥ 2/3 of Q, then anyone knowing P can understand Q and anyone knowing Q can understand P.

Where ‘P’ and ‘Q’ are words in different languages, those words are deemed as sets, and the letters of each of those words are deemed as the elements of each of those sets respectively.

Given (3), in principle, someone knowing (1) could not understand (2). Likewise, someone knowing (2) could not understand (1). Nevertheless, this is not necessarily the case. Someone knowing one of these words can understand the other one for several reasons. For instance, without the tilde, (1) also exists in Spanish (although it is not very used). So, a Spanish speaker without knowing Portuguese could understand (1). This is because, although the intersection of (1) and (2) does not fulfill (3), (1) is, without the tilde, a Spanish word with a similar meaning.

Hence, the conditional included in criterion (3) is a material conditional. In logic, material conditionals can be true even if their antecedents are false. It is enough that the consequents are true. The only case that is not permitted is the one in which the antecedent of a conditional happens and its consequent does not hold (e.g., Jeffrey, 1981). In other words, (3) provides a sufficient condition for inter-understanding, not a necessary condition for it (for this distinction, see also, e.g., Moldovan, 2009). If the antecedent of the conditional in (3) is true, inter-understanding occurs. Nonetheless, other causes can lead to inter-understanding as well. The case in which one of the words exists in the other language is, as said, an example. But other situations can also cause a correct interpretation, for instance, an appropriate context (e.g., Bonvino et al., 2015; López-Astorga, 2017).

Accordingly, it is necessary to take into account that what the present paper offers is only an initial proposal. As a proposal, it needs to keep being analyzed and developed. Perhaps, Spanish and Portuguese are the romance languages having more similarities between them. This is an advantage, but it can also lead to confusions. Very similar, or even identical, words can have different meanings in both languages. In addition, it is obvious that not only lexical overlap can have an influence on inter-understanding. The circumstances in which the word is used and the other words in the sentence can have it as well (e.g., Almeida Filho, 1995).

This implies that what (3) actually offers is just a criterion to establish the least that, in an approximate way, the speaker of a language can understand from a message in another language. The exact manner it can obtain positive results can be seen by means of words such as (4) and (5), which appear in Table 1 too.

(4) Incapacidade

(5) Incapacidad

(4) is a Portuguese word and (5) is a Spanish word. Both of them mean ‘inability’. If (4) corresponds to set E and (5) to set F, the intersection of E and F does fulfill what (3) provides.

E = {i, n, c, a, p, a, c, i, d, a, d, e}

F = {i, n, c, a, p, a, c, i, d, a, d}

E F = F = {i, n, c, a, p, a, c, i, d, a, d}

Intersection between a Portuguese text and its translation into Spanish

Accordingly, the study was based on criterion (3). The main aim was to find an approximate minimal percentage of inter-understanding between Portuguese and Spanish from that criterion. To achieve it, a Portuguese text was addressed. It is the Resumo (Abstract) of a paper in a Brazilian psychology journal (Gouveia et al., 2002). Its original Portuguese version is as follows:

Declarações condicionais com a mesma forma sintática mas conteúdos diferentes podem levar a conclusões completamente diferentes. Esse tipo de constatação tem sido apontado por alguns pesquisadores, entre os quais Wason, como evidência da incapacidade da mente humana para compreender as sentenças condicionais. No presente artigo, será discutida a importância de se considerar as influências pragmáticas no raciocínio condicional cotidiano; pois, diferentemente do raciocínio lógico, o raciocínio cotidiano não ocorre no “vazio” e, sim, inserido em um contexto onde as influências pragmáticas se fazem presentes. Inicialmente, serão apresentados alguns preceitos da lógica formal para o raciocínio condicional. Em seguida, a interpretação das sentenças condicionais na linguagem natural. Algumas evidências empíricas para a influência de fatores pragmáticos no raciocínio condicional também serão apresentadas. E, por fim, será discutida a “teoria do se” proposta por Braine e O’Brien que une lógica mental e pragmática no raciocínio cotidiano (Gouveia et al., 2002, p. 217; quotation marks in text).

In the same paper and in the same page, a translation of that Resumo into English is given:

Conditional declarations with the same syntactic form but different contents may take to completely different conclusions. This point has been highlighted by some researches (e.g., Wason) as evidence of the inability of the human mind to understand the conditional sentences. In the present article, we discuss the importance of being considered the pragmatic influences in the daily conditional reasoning; because, differently of the logical reasoning, the daily reasoning does not happen in “a vacuum”, but inserted in a context where the pragmatic influences occur. Initially, we introduce some precepts of the formal logic for the conditional reasoning. Next, we present the interpretation of the conditional sentences in the natural language. Some empiric evidences for the influence of pragmatic factors in the conditional reasoning will also be discussed. Finally, we consider the “Theory of if” proposed by Braine and O’Brien that establishes a connection between the mental and pragmatic logic in the daily reasoning (Gouveia et al., 2002, p. 217; quotation marks in text).

The study consisted of comparing each of the words in the Portuguese version to its translation into Spanish. The goal of this comparison was to check whether or not the pairs (each Portuguese word and its corresponding Spanish word) fulfill criterion (3). The next section presents the results obtained.

Results: Intersections found

The Portuguese version of the text has 144 words. It was found that, when their translations into Spanish are considered, 101 of those words meet what (3) indicates. 40 of them do not comply with criterion (3) taking into account their translations. The three remaining words are last names. Table 1 shows the 101 words following (3), their Spanish translations, and the common letters each pair has (i.e., the letters that shape the intersection between both words).

TABLE 1: Words in the Resumo in Gouveia et al. (2002) for which (3) holds if translated into Spanish, their Spanish translations, and the letters corresponding to the intersection of each pair. The table also points out, in the left column, the order of appearance of the words in the Resumo.

No.
Portuguese word
Spanish word
(Portuguese word)(Spanish word)
1
Declaraçoes
Declaraciones
Declaraoes
2
Condicionais
Condicionales
Condicionas
3
Com
Con
Co
4
Mesma
Misma
Msma
5
Forma
Forma
Forma
6
Sintática
Sintáctica
Sintatica
7
Mas
Mas
Mas
8
Conteúdos
Contenidos
Contedos
9
Diferentes
Diferentes
Diferentes
10
Levar
Llevar
Levar
11
A
A
A
12
Conclusões
Conclusiones
Conclusoes
13
Completamente
Completamente
Completamente
14
Diferentes
Diferentes
Diferentes
15
Esse
Ese
Ese
16
Tipo
Tipo
Tipo
17
De
De
De
18
Constatação
Constatación
Constatao
19
Sido
Sido
Sido
20
Apontado
Apuntado
Apntado
21
Por
Por
Por
22
Alguns
Algunos
Alguns
23
Pesquisadores
Pesquisidores
Pesquisdores
24
Entre
Entre
Entre
25
Os
Los
Os
26
Como
Como
Como
27
Evidência
Evidencia
Evidencia
28
Incapacidade
Incapacidad
Incapacidad
29
Mente
Mente
Mente
30
Humana
Humana
Humana
31
Para
Para
Para
32
Compreender
Comprender
Comprender
33
As
Las
As
34
Sentenças
Sentencias
Sentenas
35
Condicionais
Condicionales
Condicionas
36
Presente
Presente
Presente
37
Será
Será
Sera
38
Discutida
Discutida
Discutida
39
Importância
Importancia
Importancia
40
De
De
De
41
Considerar
Considerar
Considerar
42
As
Las
As
43
Influências
Influencias
Influencias
44
Pragmáticas
Pragmáticas
Pragmaticas
45
Condicional
Condicional
Condicional
46
Cotidiano
Cotidiano
Cotidiano
47
Diferentemente
Diferentemente
Diferentemente
48
Lógico
Lógico
Logico
49
Cotidiano
Cotidiano
Cotidiano
50
Não
No
No
51
Ocorre
Ocurre
Ocrre
52
Vazio
Vacío
Vacio
53
Sim
Si
54
Inserido
Insertado
Inserdo
55
Contexto
Contexto
Contexto
56
Onde
Donde
Onde
57
As
Las
As
58
Influências
Influencias
Influencias
59
Pragmáticas
Pragmáticas
Pragmaticas
60
Se
Se
Se
61
Presentes
Presentes
Presentes
62
Incialmente
Inicialmente
Inicialmente
63
Serão
Serán
Sera
64
Apresentados
Presentados
Presentados
65
Alguns
Algunos
Alguns
66
Preceitos
Preceptos
Precetos
67
Lógica
Lógica
Logica
68
Formal
Formal
Formal
69
Para
Para
Para
70
Condicional
Condicional
Condicional
71
Seguida
Seguida
Seguida
72
Interpretação
Interpretación
Interpretao
73
Sentenças
Sentencias
Sentenas
74
Condicionais
Condicionales
Condicionas
75
Linguagem
Lenguaje
Lnguae
76
Natural
Natural
Natural
77
Algumas
Algunas
Alguas
78
Evidências
Evidencias
Evidencias
79
Empíricas
Empíricas
Empiricas
80
Para
Para
Para
81
Influência
Influencia
Influencia
82
De
De
De
83
Fatores
Factores
Fatores
84
Pragmáticos
Pragmáticos
Pragmaticos
85
Condicional
Condicional
Condicional
86
Também
También
Tambe
87
Serão
Será
Sera
88
Apresentadas
Presentadas
Presentadas
89
Por
Por
Por
90
Fim
Fin
Fi
91
Será
Será
Sera
92
Discutida
Discutida
Discutida
93
Teoria
Teoría
Teoria
94
Proposta
Propuesta
Propsta
95
Por
Por
Por
96
Que
Que
Que
97
Une
Une
Une
98
Lógica
Lógica
Logica
99
Mental
Mental
Mental
100
Pragmática
Pragmática
Pragmatica
101
Cotidiano
Cotidiano
Cotidiano

Source: Own elaboration from the Resumo in Gouveia et al. (2002).

As far as the words that do not abide (3), they are indicated in Table 2. Table 2 gives the same information on its words as Table 1: order number, Portuguese Word, Spanish translation, and letters corresponding to the intersection.

TABLE 2: Words in the Resumo in Gouveia et al. (2002) for which (3) does not hold if translated into Spanish, their Spanish translations, and the letters included in the intersection of each pair. The table also points out, in the left column, the order of appearance of the words in the Resumo. ‘Ø’ stands for empty set. In this case, it means that the intersection has no elements: the words do not share letters.

No.
Portuguese word
Spanish word
(Portuguese word)(Spanish word)
1
A
La
A
2
Podem
Pueden
Pde
3
Tem
Ha
Ø
4
Quais
Cuales
Uas
5
Da
De la
Da
6
Da
De la
Da
7
No
En el
N
8
Artigo
Artículo
Artio
9
A
La
A
10
Se
Si
S
11
No
En el
N
12
Raciocínio
Razonamiento
Raonio
13
Pois
Pues
Ps
14
Do
Del
D
15
Raciocínio
Razonamiento
Raonio
16
O
El
Ø
17
Raciocínio
Razonamiento
Raonio
18
No
En el
N
19
E
Y
Ø
20
Em
En
E
21
Um
Un
U
22
Fazem
Hacen
Ae
23
Da
De la
Da
24
O
El
Ø
25
Raciocínio
Razonamiento
Raonio
26
Em
En
E
27
A
La
A
28
Das
De las
Das
29
Na
En la
Na
31
No
En el
N
32
Raciocínio
Razonamiento
Raonio
33
E
Y
Ø
34
A
La
A
35
Do
Del
D
36
Se
Si
S
37
E
Y
Ø
38
E
Y
Ø
39
No
En el
N
40
Raciocínio
Razonamiento
Raonio

Source: Own elaboration from the Resumo in Gouveia et al. (2002).

Finally, the three last names found in the text are indicated in Table 3.

TABLE 3: Last names in the Resumo in Gouveia et al. (2002). The table also points out, in the left column, the order of appearance of the words in the Resumo.

No.
Last name
1
Wason
2
Braine
3
O’Brien

Source: Own elaboration from the Resumo in Gouveia et al. (2002).

The interpretation of these results does not seem very complex. According to (3), the speaker of the other language should understand 101 words. Besides, it can also be expected that speakers of both languages will easily identify the last names (the fact that they are capitalized can help with that). So, it can be claimed that the words that can be correctly interpreted are, at least, 104. Given that the text has 144 words, the speaker of any of the two languages will understand, at a minimum, 72.2% of the words. Thus, the percentage of words that will not be probably savvied is 27,8%.

Conclusions and general discussion

Therefore, if (3) is a suitable criterion to assess inter-understanding, it can be stated that a Spanish speaker tends to understand Portuguese, and that a Portuguese speaker tends to understand Spanish. To assert this is not a great novelty (as it is shown, e.g., by several references included in this paper). However, the study described can make an additional point about this issue: (3) is intended to be a more or less objective criterion to evaluate the intelligibility between languages. One might intuitively think that cognates will be understood in most cases. Nevertheless, (3) tries to be a general rule to foresee when the meaning of a word will be identified and when not. From this perspective, it can be said that the minimal percentage of inter-understanding between Portuguese and Spanish is around 72,2%.

Nonetheless, this should be assumed as a provisional hypothesis. Further studies and research are required to unequivocally support it. First, the study above only dealt with written text, and not with oral communication. On the other hand, the study presented an ideal situation. It assumes that all of the Portuguese speakers know all of the Portuguese words in Table 1 and Table 2. Likewise, it also presumed that all of the Spanish speakers know all of the Spanish words in those very tables. These points, and, of course, aspects such as the circumstances in which communication happens, should be taken into account in future studies.

In the same way, (3) points out 2/3 as a percentage of intersection conventionally. The suitable percentage might be different. Perhaps only more empirical works could enlighten with regard to this. Those works would need participants and have to verify to what extent it is correct the following: when the intersection of the letters of two words coming from two different languages is equal to or greater than 2/3, speakers of both languages can comprehend those words (provided that the two words have the same meaning in the two languages). Obviously, this could apply not only to Portuguese and Spanish, but also to any other pair of languages.

In addition, even supposing that (3) is correct, as indicated, it would be a criterion to obtain only minimal percentages of inter-understanding. As explained with (1) and (2), two words can be incompatible with (3). However, speakers of the other language can understand one of them because it also exists in their language (although it is less used) (to a discussion and a greater development of possibilities such as these, see, e.g., Almeida Filho, 1995). Furthermore, as also indicated, context can play a role in inter-understanding too. For example, pelos in Portuguese is a contraction of por (‘by’) and os (‘the’ when it refers to plural masculine nouns). The problem with this word is that there is a Spanish word that is identical to it, but with a different meaning: the Spanish pelos is translated into English by ‘hairs’. Hence, in principle, it is difficult that a Spanish speaker notes the meaning of pelos in Portuguese (the Spanish translation of the Portuguese pelos is ‘por los’, and a contraction is not possible). Nevertheless, based on the theory of mental models, it has been argued that a Spanish speaker can identify the meaning of the Portuguese word pelos because of context (López-Astorga, 2017). Therefore, it has to be admitted that (3) is not the only criterion, but just one more of the factors having an influence on inter-understanding.

Besides, as it is mentioned in many linguistic works about different issues, it is always positive to address more extensive corpora and related to varying fields. The text selected in the study above comes from a psychology paper. Maybe it would be advisable to review, for example, whether (3) can also be accepted when the text belongs to another subject area.

In any case, the proposal is that (3) is provisionally assumed to lead future research. Those researches will probably tint it. They will almost certainly show to what extent it is suitable to accept that criterion as well.

Acknowledgments and Funding Information

PIA Ciencias Cognitivas, Centro de Investigación en Ciencias Cognitivas, Instituto de Estudios Humanísticos, Universidad de Talca.

Conflict of interest

The author declares that there is no conflict of interest with any institution or association of any kind. Likewise, the Universidad Católica Luis Amigó is not responsible for the handling of copyrights that the authors make in their articles, therefore, the veracity and completeness of quotations and references are the responsibility of the authors.

References

Almeida Filho, J. C. P. (Org.) (1995). Português para estrangeiros: Interface com o espanhol. Pontes Editores.

Aparecida Duarte, C. (2005). Diferencias de usos gramaticales entre español/portugués. Editorial Edinumen.

Bertelli, A. (2016). Intercomprensión e identidad cultural: Consideraciones acerca de procesos interculturales en el aprendizaje receptivo plurilingüe. In C. Quintana Mejía, A. Bertelli, B. Peña, M. I. Cárdenas, A. Merlo, G. Jassen, J. Pardo González, & S. Arango Moreno (Eds.), Entre lenguas y culturas: Prácticas pedagógicas. Volumen 1 (pp. 39-66). Ediciones Unidandes.

Bonvino, E., Caddéo, S., Vilaginés Serra, E., & Pippa, S. (2015). Eurom5. Ler e compreender 5 línguas românicas. Leer y entender 5 lenguas románicas. Llegir i entendre 5 llengües romàniques. Leggere e capire 5 lingue romanze. Lire et comprendre 5 langues romanes. Ulrico Hoeply; SGEL Libros; La maison du dictionnaire.

Byrne, R. M. J., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (2020). If and or: Real and counterfactual possibilities in their truth and probability. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 46(4), 760-780. https://doi.org/10.1037/xlm0000756

Ceolin, R. (2003). Falsos amigos estruturais entre o português e o castelhano. Ianua. Revista Philologica Romanica, 4, 39-48 https://raco.cat/index.php/Ianua/article/view/113862

Chávez Solís, C. F., & Erazo Muñoz, A. (2014). Propuestas plurilingües para la integración latinoamericana: la intercomprensión en lenguas emparentadas como práctica de comunicación y educación. SURES, 3, 1-17. https://revistas.unila.edu.br/sures/article/view/139

Decandio, F., & Dolz, J. (2015). La correspondencia escolar electrónica: un enfoque didáctico para el desarrollo de la intercomprensión entre lenguas románicas. In I. García-Azkoaga & I. Idiazabal (Eds.), Para una ingeniería didáctica de la educación plurilingüe (pp. 265-289). Servicio de Publicaciones de la UPV/EHU.

Gouveia, E. L., Roazzi, A., Moutinho, K., Bompastor Borges Dias, M. G., & O’Brien, D. P. (2002). Raciocínio condicional: influências pragmáticas. Estudos de Psicologia, 7(2), 217-225. https://www.redalyc.org/pdf/261/26170203.pdf

Jeffrey, R. (1981). Formal Logic: Its Scope and Limits. McGraw-Hill.

Khemlani, S., Byrne, R. M. J., & Johnson-Laird, P. N. (2018). Facts and possibilities: A model-based theory of sentential reasoning. Cognitive Science, 42(6), 1887-1924. https://doi.org/10.1111/cogs.12634

López-Astorga, M. (2017). Linguistic inter-understanding gives evidence in favor of the mental models theory: Induction and comprehension. Aufklärung, 4(2), 11-20. https://www.redalyc.org/pdf/4715/471555235004.pdf

López-Astorga, M. & Torres-Bravo, L. D. (2020). Formal inferences and their relations to knowledge acquisition: Mental models and semantic links. Principia, 24(2), 325-331. https://doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2020v24n2p325

Moldovan, A. (2009). Pragmatic considerations in the interpretation of denying the antecedent. Informal Logic, 29(3), 309-326. https://doi.org/10.22329/il.v29i3.2846

Peano, G. (1903). De latino sine flexione. Lingua auxiliare internationale. Revue de Mathématiques (Rivista di Matematica), 8, 74-83.

Peano, G. (1904). Vocabulario de latino internationale comparato cum Anglo, Franco, Germano, Hispano, Italo, Russo, Graeco et Sanscrito. Tip della Rivista di matematica.

Vázquez Diéguez, I. (2011). Sobre algunos falsos cognados español portugués: Factores lingüísticos y sociales reflejados en la semántica. Epos, 27, 33-48 https://dialnet.unirioja.es/servlet/articulo?codigo=3971258

Notas de autor

Miguel López-Astorga

Ph.D. in Logic and Philosophy of Sciences. Instituto de Estudios Humanísticos “Juan Ignacio Molina”, Universidad de Talca, Talca (Chile). Correo electrónico: milopez@utalca.cl, ORCiD: https://orcid.org/0000-0002-6004-0587